Bhartrhari’s Paradox points out a tricky situation: if we say that some things can’t be named, the very act of calling them “unnameable” actually gives them a name. This creates a direct conflict with the original idea that those things have no name.
If cats always land on their feet and buttered toast always lands buttered side down, what would happen if you strapped buttered toast to the back of a cat – buttered side up – and it falls off a table?
It makes you think, doesn’t it? It’s a contradiction that might even confuse you. But some people refuse to believe that problems are unsolvable. And thus, there must be a concrete answer. So, if you were to ask certain scientists the question, they’d say the cat would never land. Instead, it would stop falling at some point above the floor. As it tries to orient its feet against the attraction of the butter to the floor, the cat would begin spinning – and it would never stop. Basically, buttered cat = perpetual motion machine. Problem solved. Or was it?
The Buttered Cat Paradox is one of many logical paradoxes. Confusing conundrums that contradict themselves. And seem to have no concrete solution. Until someone comes up with something that sort of makes sense, but also doesn’t really. Bored Panda has put together a list of the best ones. Many of these mind-bending puzzles may make your brain hurt. So buckle up, keep scrolling and upvote the ones that turn your reality upside down.
Not everything in life is meant to make sense. Or is it? The answer depends largely on who you ask. In the blue corner, those who are willing to not sweat the small stuff and let some sh*t slide. In the red corner, team “there must be a logical explanation for this utterly confusing contradiction.”
Henry Dudeney once wrote: “A child asked, ‘Can God do everything?’ On receiving an affirmative reply, she at once said: ‘Then can He make a stone so heavy that He can’t lift it?'”
Some would reply “yes.” Others would say “no.” A few might warn the child not to question faith.
The Paradox of the Court presents a circular dilemma. A law student promises to pay his teacher only after winning his first case. When the teacher sues the student for payment (before the student has won any cases), a paradox emerges: if the teacher loses this lawsuit, the student has now won his first case (by virtue of the lawsuit concluding, even if he loses the payment demand) and thus must pay. However, if the student wins the lawsuit (meaning he doesn’t have to pay based on this suit), he still hasn’t won his “first case” according to the original agreement, and so shouldn’t have to pay – yet winning this suit is his first win.
The Ship of Theseus paradox explores identity through change. If you replace every single component of a ship, one by one, is it still the original ship? This seems plausible. However, if you then take all the old, original pieces and reassemble them into a ship, that vessel also has a strong claim to being the original ship, creating a puzzle about which one, if either, truly is the same ship you started with.
If I told you “This sentence is a lie,” would you believe me? It’s the classic liar paradox, another contradictory statement that might get your head spinning. It’s derived from something the Cretan prophet Epimenides said in the 6th century BCE: “All Cretans are liars.”
“If Epimenides’ statement is taken to imply that all statements made by Cretans are false, then, since Epimenides was a Cretan, his statement is false (i.e., not all Cretans are liars),” explains Britannica.
If the sentence is true, then it is false, and if it is false, then it is true. Let that sink in, or swirl about, as you keep scrolling…
The Hedgehog’s Dilemma, sometimes called the porcupine dilemma, uses a metaphor to illustrate the challenges of human intimacy. It describes hedgehogs wanting to huddle together for warmth in cold weather, yet their sharp spines inevitably cause pain when they get too close. This illustrates how, despite a mutual desire for closeness and connection, the very act of getting close can lead to unavoidable hurt, forcing a difficult balance between connection and self-preservation.
The Abilene Paradox occurs when a group of people collectively agrees to a course of action that none of them individually want. This happens because each member mistakenly believes their own preferences are contrary to the group’s desires, leading to a breakdown in communication. Consequently, individuals don’t voice objections and may even express support for an outcome they secretly oppose, all while thinking they are aligning with the majority.
The Hedgehog’s Dilemma is a logical paradox that actually might make sense to many of us. It’s tells us that when hedgehogs or porcupines get too close to each other, they end up getting hurt or hurting each other. It’s a metaphor for the human inability to break down all of one’s inner walls towards others.
“A number of porcupines huddled together for warmth on a cold day in winter, but, as they began to prick one another with their quills, they were obliged to disperse. However, the cold drove them together again, when just the same thing happened. At last, after many turns of huddling and dispersing, they discovered that they would be best off by remaining at a little distance from one another,” wrote philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer.
The Drinker Paradox is a logic puzzle saying that in any pub, there’s always one customer who makes this statement true: if that particular customer has a drink, then everyone in the pub has a drink. This seems odd, but it works out because if all customers are already drinking, then any drinking customer makes the statement true. If even one customer isn’t drinking, then that non-drinking customer is the special one; since the “if they are drinking” part isn’t true for them, the whole idea automatically holds up logically.
Schopenhauer adds that in the same way, humans come together seeking society, only to be mutually repelled by the many prickly and disagreeable qualities of their nature.
“The moderate distance which they at last discover to be the only tolerable condition of intercourse is the code of politeness and fine manners, and those who transgress it are roughly told—in the English phrase—to keep their distance,” wrote the philosopher. “By this arrangement, the mutual need of warmth is only very moderately satisfied, but then people do not get pricked. A man who has some heat in himself prefers to remain outside, where he will neither prick other people nor get pricked himself.”
The Paradox of Free Choice highlights a weird outcome when we use a basic logic rule with permissions. If you’re told “You may have an apple,” logic says it’s also true to say “You may have an apple or you may have a pear.” The problem is, this same logic could then imply “You may have an apple or you may fly to the moon,” making it sound like you’ve been given permission for something totally random and unintended, just by adding an “or.”
The Lottery Paradox points out a conflict in what seems reasonable to believe. In a big lottery with only one winner, it makes sense to think that any single ticket you pick probably isn’t the winner. However, it doesn’t make sense to believe that none of the tickets will win, because we know there has to be one winning ticket.
Scrolling through this list of logical paradoxes brings one in particular to mind. It’s attributed to the ancient Greek philosopher Socrates. And he said, “The only thing that I know, is that I know nothing.”
Taken literally, it would seem like a lie. Or a paradox. But it points to a deeper truth. We learn something new every day. We cannot possibly know everything. And challenging our thinking by seeking answers is an invaluable way to give our brains a good workout. Albeit sometimes a rather mind-bending one.
The Raven Paradox is the idea that observing a green apple actually increases the likelihood of all ravens being black. This seemingly odd conclusion comes from a rule of logic where the statement “All ravens are black” is considered logically the same as “All non-black things are non-ravens.” Since a green apple is a non-black thing that is also a non-raven, observing it supports the second statement, and therefore, by strict logic, it also supports the first statement about ravens, even though it feels unrelated.
The Crocodile Dilemma describes a no-win situation: a crocodile steals a child and tells the parent it will return the child only if the parent correctly predicts whether the crocodile will return the child or not. If the parent predicts the crocodile will return the child, and the crocodile was going to do so, it keeps its word. But if the crocodile wasn’t going to, it now must return the child to make the parent’s prediction wrong, yet also not return it to keep its promise of only returning it on a correct prediction. Conversely, if the parent predicts the crocodile will not return the child, and the crocodile wasn’t going to, it’s a correct prediction, so the child should be returned, but this makes the prediction wrong. It creates a loop where the crocodile can’t make a decision that aligns with its own rule.
The paradox “I know that I know nothing” famously associated with Socrates, encapsulates a profound philosophical stance. After the Oracle of Delphi declared him the wisest person, Socrates, deeply aware of his own lack of knowledge, concluded that his wisdom lay not in possessing knowledge, but in recognizing his own ignorance. This self-awareness differentiated him from others who mistakenly believed they knew things they did not.
The Knower Paradox arises from a sentence that refers to itself, specifically one that states, “This sentence is not known.” The problem is, if the sentence is true (meaning it really isn’t known), then we’ve just established its truth, so we now know it, which makes the original statement false. But if the sentence is false (meaning it is known), then what it says about itself (that it’s not known) is incorrect, leading back to a contradiction.
The Sorites Paradox questions how we define vague terms like “heap.” It points out that if you have a heap of sand and remove one grain, it’s still a heap. If you continue removing grains one by one, eventually you won’t have a heap. The paradox lies in the difficulty of identifying the exact point at which removing a single grain of sand transforms the heap into a non-heap.
The Buttered Cat Paradox is a humorous thought experiment based on combining two common sayings: that cats always land on their feet, and that buttered toast always lands butter-side down. The paradox emerges when you imagine attaching a piece of buttered toast (with the buttered side facing up) to a cat’s back and then dropping the cat. The two adages create a conflict, leading to a comical debate about how the cat would, or could, possibly land.
The paradox of the “Intentionally Blank Page” occurs when a page in a document has the words “This page intentionally left blank” printed on it. The very presence of this text means the page is no longer truly blank, creating a direct contradiction with the statement itself.
A Catch-22 describes a frustrating, no-win situation where you need something you can only get if you don’t actually need it. For example, a soldier might want to be declared insane to get out of dangerous combat, but the very act of wanting to avoid combat is seen as a sign of sanity, meaning they won’t be declared insane. It’s a rule or situation that traps you in a loop.
The Temperature Paradox, also known as Partee’s paradox, highlights how language can be tricky. It presents an argument like this: “The temperature is ninety. The temperature is rising. Therefore, ninety is rising.” The conclusion “ninety is rising” is clearly wrong. The paradox arises because the word “temperature” is used in two different ways: first, to state a specific value (ninety), and second, to describe a changing condition (rising). The number ninety itself cannot “rise” in the same way a temperature can.
The Surprise Test Paradox explores a puzzle about expectations. Imagine a teacher tells students they will have a surprise test sometime next week, meaning they won’t know which day it will be. Students might reason that if the test hasn’t happened by Thursday, it must be Friday, so Friday wouldn’t be a surprise. Ruling out Friday, they might then reason it can’t be Thursday (as it would then be expected), and so on, seemingly eliminating all possible days. Yet, if the teacher gives the test on Wednesday, it still feels like a surprise, creating the paradox.
The Barber Paradox describes a situation with a male barber who shaves all men in town who do not shave themselves, and only those men. The question then arises: does the barber shave himself? If he does shave himself, he violates his rule of only shaving men who don’t shave themselves. But if he doesn’t shave himself, then according to his rule, he must shave himself, creating an unsolvable contradiction.
The Berry Paradox emerges from considering an expression like “The smallest positive integer not definable in under sixty letters.” The problem is that this very phrase, which has fewer than sixty letters (for instance, fifty-seven letters), actually defines that specific integer. This creates a contradiction, because the phrase defines a number using fewer than sixty letters, while the number it’s supposed to describe is one that allegedly cannot be defined in under sixty letters.
The Grelling–Nelson Paradox questions whether the word “heterological” (which means “not applicable to itself” or “does not describe itself”) is, in fact, heterological. If “heterological” is heterological, then it doesn’t apply to itself, meaning it’s not heterological – a contradiction. Conversely, if “heterological” is not heterological (meaning it does apply to itself), then by its own definition, it should be heterological, leading to another contradiction.
The Opposite Day paradox arises from the statement, “It is opposite day today.” If this statement is true, then because it’s opposite day, the statement must actually mean its opposite: “It is not opposite day today,” which is a direct contradiction. On the other hand, if you assume the statement “It is opposite day today” is false, it would mean it’s a normal day. On a normal day, that statement would simply be false, meaning it isn’t opposite day, but this doesn’t resolve the problem of trying to declare opposite day in the first place, as the declaration itself becomes self-refuting.
Russell’s Paradox asks: does the set of all those sets that do not contain themselves as a member, actually contain itself? If this special set does contain itself, then by its own definition, it shouldn’t (because it only contains sets that don’t contain themselves). But if this special set doesn’t contain itself, then by its own definition, it should (because it’s a set that doesn’t contain itself, and it’s supposed to gather all such sets). This creates an inescapable contradiction.
The Barbershop Paradox explores the tricky consequences of believing that “if one of two simultaneous assumptions leads to a contradiction, the other assumption is also disproved.” This very supposition—that proving one idea wrong automatically proves the other wrong when they’re considered together—can itself lead to paradoxical or illogical outcomes.
This paradox, also known as Carroll’s paradox, highlights a problem with the nature of logical deduction. It suggests that if you always need to add a new premise stating that a specific conclusion can be deduced from the existing premises, then you can never actually reach the conclusion, leading to an infinite regress. The core idea is that an inference rule (the method of reasoning) cannot simply be treated as another factual premise (something true or false) without running into this endless loop.
The Liar Paradox, also known as the Epimenides paradox, emerges from self-referential statements such as “This sentence is false” or a person declaring “I am lying.” A contradiction arises when attempting to assign a truth value: if the statement “This sentence is false” is true, then what it asserts (that it’s false) must be correct, meaning it’s actually false. Conversely, if you assume the statement is false, then its claim (that it’s false) is incorrect, meaning it must be true, leading to another inescapable contradiction.